Skip to main content
Log in

Revaluing the behaviorist ghost in enactivism and embodied cognition

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite its short historical moment in the sun, behaviorism has become something akin to a theoria non grata, a position that dare not be explicitly endorsed. The reasons for this are complex, of course, and they include sociological factors which we cannot consider here, but to put it briefly: many have doubted the ambition to establish law-like relationships between mental states and behavior that dispense with any sort of mentalistic or intentional idiom, judging that explanations of intelligent behavior require reference to qualia and/or mental events. Today, when behaviorism is discussed at all, it is usually in a negative manner, either as an attempt to discredit an opponent’s view via a reductio, or by enabling a position to distinguish its identity and positive claims by reference to what it is (allegedly) not. In this paper, however, we argue that the ghost of behaviorism is present in influential, contemporary work in the field of embodied and enactive cognition, and even in aspects of the phenomenological tradition that these theorists draw on. Rather than take this to be a problem for these views as some have (e.g. Block, J Philos 102:259–272, 2005; Jacob, Rev Philos Psychol 2(3):519–540, 2011; O’Brien and Opie, Philos 43:723–729, 2015), we argue that once the behaviorist dimensions are clarified and distinguished from the straw-man version of the view, it is in fact an asset, one which will help with task of setting forth a scientifically reputable version of enactivism and/or philosophical behaviorism that is nonetheless not brain-centric but behavior-centric. While this is a bit like “the enemy of my enemy is my friend” strategy, as Shaun Gallagher notes (in Philos Stud 176(3):839–8512019), with the shared enemy of behaviorism and enactivism being classical Cartesian views and/or orthodox cognitivism in its various guises, the task of this paper is to render this alliance philosophically plausible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We are not arguing that early behaviorism wholly succeeded in understanding animals and that the only problem left for it was explaining distinctively human skills and abilities. On the contrary, it is arguable that contemporary enactivist work delivers better on the behaviorist promise regarding understanding the continuity between human and animal behavior, showing that both cases require a major role being given to perspectival indexicality. In addition, enactivism can enrich behaviorism’s understanding of the reciprocal causal relations between an organism and its milieu, but making that case is another paper.

  2. Fully explicating this is beyond us here, but see Reynolds (2019) for an account of how phenomena like mind, mentality, and morality might be understood in relation to animal behavior.

  3. A book seemingly dedicated to the topic, entitled Behaviorism and Phenomenology (ed. Wann 1964), refers to phenomenology as being related to the psychological investigation of the phenomenal, rather than the more accepted interpretation of phenomenology we are using in this paper.

  4. We acknowledge that this account lacks an explanation for the phenomenal character of pain, but this is not different from other naturalist accounts such as functionalist ones (see Jackson and Pettit 1988, for a critique see Block 1978). Along similar lines it could be argued that the super-super-Spartans case once again dismisses the behaviorist moves we are making. However, this would lead to a genuine worry that the notion of pain has been bracketed away to the realm of the purely mental. If there is no trace of pain beyond the pure sensation, that is, no trace would be detectable in an agent’s physiology or within a larger historical context, the concept of pain seems to operate in a mind/body dichotomy in which the mind leaves no trace on the body.

  5. Two quotes from Shaun Gallagher’s recent book, Enactivist Interventions, are also suggestive of behaviorist commitments:

    mental skills such as reflection, problem solving, decision making, and so on, (are) enactive non-representational forms of embodied coping that are emergent from a pre-predicative perceptual ordering of differentiations and similarities (Gallagher 2017, p. 202).

    and

    with respect to PC models, enactivist views that emphasise a more holistic system of brain-body-environment would clearly favor a move away from internalist and intellectualist vocabularies (and conceptions of) ‘hypotheses’, ‘inference’ and ‘representation’ in favor of more embodied terms like ‘adjustment’, ‘attunement’ and ‘affordance’ (Gallagher 2017, p. 21).

    These terms are not only more embodied, but they also have a behaviorist dimension that is apparent even by attending to the words alone: the organism adjusts, attunes, and finds this or that affordance available. And the appeal to holism that characterizes Gallagher’s work is also part of a certain behaviorist tradition, rather than antithetical to it, as we have seen.

  6. There is something paradoxical about the idea of a behaviorist zombie, whatever bracketing of the mental, the intentional, etc., might be attempted by some versions of behaviorism. The very idea of zombies derives from functionalist criticisms of behaviorism (e.g. in Chalmers), rather than from behaviorism itself. They depend on the idea of “mere” or meaningless physical behavior, but neither behaviorism, nor phenomenology, nor enactivist biology, give these thought experiments and their insights into possibility much credence.

  7. We might also have chosen to look at the enactivist view of perception and cognition, which has been criticized by Block for its behaviorism (2005). Block criticizes Noë’s (2004) enactive account of action in perception, complaining that the view is behaviorist due to having no account of internal processes mediating between sensory inputs and outputs, but we agree with the enactivist-cum-behaviorist insight that it is not clear that explanatory priority should be accorded to the internal processes.

  8. Kirchhoff (2015) shows that the objection depends on a particular metaphysical picture for its coherence (e.g. a picture of synchronic rather than diachronic emergence).

  9. Perhaps Varga effectively admits something like this in other work when he comes to embrace “embodied situationism” (see Varga 2018).

  10. A reviewer of this paper has noted that although it is often maintained that psychopaths are highly intelligent and expert manipulators, if we look at specific cases they are often quite crude in their machinations and may well betray themselves behaviorally, their colleagues and community often allow them to get away with it because they stick to certain conventions and norms. In other words, the deceived play as much of a role in the deception as the deceiver.

  11. Indeed, while many contemporary phenomenologists (or enactivists drawing on phenomenology) have insisted that they are not advocating behaviorism (e.g. Romano 2016, p. 340; Gallagher 2017, pp. 69–70; Morris 2010; Thompson 2007, p. 50; Noë 2004, pp. 32–33), they clearly perceive sufficient proximity to behaviorism such that they are motivated to (attempt to) establish the distance. In addition, we think the contrast they draw with behaviorism often depends on a straw-man version of the view. The precise behaviorist target is often difficult to identify, and it rarely countenances the sort of holistic position we have traced from Ryle, and both radical and molar behaviorism.

  12. Others have recognized that the work of Mead (Rosenthal and Bourgeois 1991) and Ryle (Jackson 2011; Evans 1983) is aligned with Merleau-Ponty. They have done so by downplaying Mead and Ryle’s respective commitments to behaviorism. We agree with the connections they have forged, but think that they should embrace non-reductive behaviorism. Edward Tolman’s work is also important here, as Merleau-Ponty himself recognizes.

  13. Ryle sometimes himself recognized this, both early in his career when he drew on Heidegger’s treatment of the ready-to-hand/present-at-hand distinction in his own accounts of know-how and knowledge-that, and later in his career when two pages of his 15 page autobiographical essay are devoted to phenomenology (cf. Thomasson 2002; Chase and Reynolds 2017).

References

  • Aizawa, K. (2017). Cognition and behavior. Synthese, 194(11), 4269–4288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alksnis, N. (2015). A dilemma or a challenge? Assessing the all-star team in a wider context. Philosophia, 43(3), 669–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2019). Enactivism, pragmatism… behaviorism? Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 807–818. (Forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. (2005). Understanding behaviorism: Behavior, culture and evolution (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. In W. Savage (Ed.), Perception and cognition (pp. 9–261). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2005). Review of Noë, action in perception. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 259–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. (2003). Heidegger’s analytic: Interpretation, discourse, and authenticity in being and time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chase, J., & Reynolds, J. (2017). Russell, Ryle, and phenomenology: An alternative parsing of the way. In A. Preston (Ed.), Analytic philosophy: An interpretive history (pp. 52–69). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chase, P., & Watson, A. C. (2004). Unconscious cognition and behaviorism. The Journal of Mind and Behavior, 25(2), 145–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corriveau, M. (1972). Phenomenology, psychology, and radical behaviorism: Skinner and Merleau-Ponty on behavior. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 3(1), 7–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danón, L. (2018). Neo-pragmatism, primitive intentionality and animal minds. Philosophia. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-018-9963-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Day, W. F. (1969). On certain similarities between the Philosophical Investigations of Ludwig Wittgenstein and the operationism of B. F. Skinner. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 12, 489–506.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1978). Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. New York: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (1990). Being in the word. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002a). Intelligence without representation—Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation the relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002b). Refocusing the question: Can there be skillful coping without propositional representations or brain representations? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 413–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (1983). Behaviorism as existentialism? Ryle and Merleau-Ponty on the mind. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 14(1), 65–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faulconer, J. E., & Williams, R. N. (1985). Temporality in human action: An alternative to positivism and historicism. American Psychologist, 50, 1179–1188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1963). Materialism and the mind-body problem. Review of Metaphysics, 17, 49–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1965). On the “meaning” of scientific terms. Journal of Philosophy, 62(10), 266–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finn, D. R. (1971). Putnam and logical behaviourism. Mind, 80, 432–436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1994). The elm and the expert: Mentalese and its semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T. (2018). Ecology of the brain: The phenomenology and biology of the embodied mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2019). Replies to Barrett, Corris and Chemero, and Hutto. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 839–851. (Forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Varga, S. (2014). Social constraints on the direct perception of emotions and intentions. Topoi, 33, 185–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). Intentionality all-stars. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and embedded. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind (pp. 207–239). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hocutt, M. (1985). Spartans, strawmen, and symptoms. Behaviorism, 13(2), 87–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hocutt, M. (1986). Witches and behaviorists: A reply to Robinson and Boyer. Behaviorism, 14(1), 97–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, G. B. (2011). Skill in Ryle and Merleau-Ponty. In K. Semonovitch & N. DeRoo (Eds.), Merleau-Ponty at the limits of art, religion. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, G. B. (2014). Skillful action in peripersonal space. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13(2), 313–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, G. B. (2018). Seeing what is not seen. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(3), 503–519.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1988). Functionalism and broad content. Mind, 97(387), 381–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (2011). The direct-perception model of empathy: A critique. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(3), 519–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2006). Philosophy of mind. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Extended cognition & the causal-constitutive fallacy: In search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 320–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knapp, T. (1989). Willard F. Day, Jr. (1926–1989). Behaviorism, 17(1), 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2018). Direct social perception. In A. Newen, L. de Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), The oxford handbook of cognition: Embodied, enactive, extended (pp. 301–320). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J., & Overgaard, S. (2012). Seeing subjectivity: defending a perceptual account of other minds. ProtoSociology, 47, 239–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvale, S., & Grenness, C. E. (1967). Skinner and sartre: Towards a radical phenomenology of behavior? Review of Existential Psychology and Psychiatry, 7, 128–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leudar, I., & Costall, A. (2004). On the persistence of the ‘Problem of Other Minds’ in psychology: Chomsky, Grice and theory of mind. Theory & Psychology, 14(5), 601–621.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self and society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010) Child psychology and pedagogy: The sorbonne lectures 1949–52 (T. Welsh, Trans.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern UP.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception (D. Landes, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Morag, T. (2016). Emotion, imagination and the limits of reason. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morf, M. E. (1998). Sartre, Skinner, and the compatibilist freedom to be authentically. Behavior and Philosophy, 26, 29–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (2010). Empirical and phenomenological studies of embodied cognition. In D. Schicking & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Handbook of embodied cognition. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myin, E. (2016). Perception as something we do. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(5–6), 80–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myin, E., & Zahnoun, F. (2018). Reincarnating the identity theory. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 2044.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2015). Intentionality lite or analog content? Philosophia, 43, 723–729. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9623-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olen, P. (2018). The varieties and origins of wilfrid sellars’ behaviorism. In A. Nunziante & L. Corti (Eds.), Sellars and the history of modern philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Packer, M. J. (1985). Hermeneutic inquiry in the study of human conduct. American Psychologist, 50, 1081–1093.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1963). Brains and behavior. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy: Second series. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H., & Frankel, M. (2009). Taking pragmatism seriously. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 92(1), 131–137. https://doi.org/10.1901/jeab.2009.92-131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V. S., & Hirstein, W. (2000). Three laws of qualia. In S. Gallagher & J. Shear (Eds.), Models of the self. New York: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, J. (2019). Temporal naturalism: Reconciling the “4Ms” and points of view within a robust liberal naturalism. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-019-09613-w. (Forthcoming).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2016). At the heart of reason. Evanston, IL: Northwestern UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, S., & Bourgeois, P. (1991). Mead and Merleau-Ponty: Toward a common vision. Albany: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1991). A defense of behaviorism. Behavior and Philosophy, 19(1), 93–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009). The concept of mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachs, C. B. (2014). Intentionality and the myths of the given. London: Pickering & Chatto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharff, J. L. (1999). Skinner’s reinforcement theory: A Heideggerian assessment of its empirical success and its philosophical failure. Behavior and Philosophy, 27(1), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1932). Drives and drive strength. Journal of General Psychology, 6, 23–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1935). Two types of conditioned reflex and a pseudo-type. Journal of General Psychology, 12, 66–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1937). Two types of conditioned reflex: A reply to Konorsky and Miller. Journal of General Psychology, 16, 272–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviorism. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. (1963). Philosophy and scientific realism. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, R. (2006). The inner life of a rational agent: In defence of philosophical behaviourism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanney, J. (2005). Une cartographie des concepts mentaux. In G. Ryle (Ed.), The concept of mind (pp. 7–70). Paris: Payot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanney, J. (2009a). Reasons as Non-causal, Context-placing Explanations. In Sandis, C. (Ed.), New essays on the explanation of action (pp 94–111). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanney, J. (2009b). Gilbert ryle. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2009 Edition). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/ryle/. Retrieved 14 Jan 2015.

  • Thomasson, A. (2002). Phenomenology and the development of analytic philosophy. Southern Journal of Philosophy, XL, 115–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in animals and men. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolman, E. C. (1951). Behavior and psychological man. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varga, S. (2018). Embodied situationism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(2), 271–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wann, T. W. (Ed.). (1964). Behaviorism and phenomenology: Contrasting bases for modern psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, L. M. (2001). Human neural plasticity. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(8), 325–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to acknowledge the seminar audiences at Deakin, Melbourne, and Monash universities, for their helpful feedback on this paper. In addition, we are appreciative of some insightful suggestions for improvement from the reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nikolai Alksnis.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alksnis, N., Reynolds, J. Revaluing the behaviorist ghost in enactivism and embodied cognition. Synthese 198, 5785–5807 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02432-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02432-1

Keywords

Navigation